In an earlier post, Yusef suggested that there's a certain kind of critique, a
Platonic critique, which is distinguished by the importance of "testing of claims and claimants." I want to take up a minor disagreement with this assessment, but it is always the minor points on which everything else turns.
Platonism (but not necessarily Plato himself) is the enemy for the historical-libidinal materialist tradition (Nietzsche, Foucault, Deleuze, Guattari, Negri). Why Platonism? And what is Platonism?
In
Nietzsche and Philosophy, Deleuze gives us the contrast: it is Socrates (speaking through Plato) who asks, "what is . . .?" Socrates/Plato asks for the definition, the identity, of the thing (of love, of virtue, of courage, of beauty, of justice). But Dionysus (speaking through Nietzsche) asks, "who is the one who says . . . ?" Dionysos makes the
radically "relativizing" move by risking acknowledgement of the perspective which informs the assertion being made. Where Plato is the great de-contextualizer and de-perspectivizer, Nietzsche is the opposite.
But at the same time we cannot ignore the ways in which "the opposite of Plato" is itself another of Nietzsche's many masks . . . the hermeneutic problems multiply into a swarm of hornets when one considers how Nietzsche characterizes metaphysics as "the faith in opposite values," in
Human, All-too-Human and in
Beyond Good and Evil. The "faith in opposite values" is the faith that reason could not have emerged from the irrational, that what is noble and good could not have emerged from what is base and bad. If Nietzsche is "the opposite of Plato," then he is
the opposite of opposition, and he himself is only one more metaphysician. I suspect that something like this underpins Heidegger's reading of Nietzsche as "the last metaphysician" -- the thinker whose opposition to opposition made opposition impossible.
Deleuze, on the other hand, attempts to side-step this problematic by adopting the Spinozist assertion,
Non opposita sed diversa -- "Not opposed but different" -- as the watchword for a very different kind of ontology, a flat ontology of virtual multiplicities and processes of actualization. And corresponding to this ontology is a different kind of critique than the Platonic critique. The Platonic critique seeks the heights; its
mere inversion, which is the Heideggerian, seeks the depths. What neither Plato nor Heidegger know how to do is how to say
on the surface.
But how might a critique stay on the surface and yet be critical? There is a model for this that is even older than Plato, against whom Plato is
reacting: the
History of the Peloponessian War of Thucydides. One need only think of his work as "On the
Geneaology of the Peloponessian War" to see the convergence with Nietzsche. Thucydides asks, "who is the one who says . . .?" in the famous dialogue of the Athenians with the Miletans, in Pericles' funeral oration, and throughout the
History.
So here, too, there is a "testing of claims and claimants" -- but of a very different kind.
Where Plato looks for Ideas, Thucydides looks for the tangle of motives and desires. It was Foucault who said, "People know what they do, and they frequently know why they do what they do, but what they don't know is what what they do does." This is a Thucydidean thought, and one alien not only to Plato, but also to Aristotle, who rated history as even further from truth than poetry is.
If one considers the Greece of Democritus and Thucydides, it is clear that Plato is
reactionary. But what makes him reactionary? It is not that he demands clarity of definitions, but that he uses this demand
in the service of myth. No careful reader of Plato can fail to be amazed at the parade of myths, metaphors, and stories in the Platonic dialogues. Everywhere Socrates says, "I don't know
what it is, but I can tell you
what it is like": the Myth of Er in
Republic, the story of Eros in
Symposium, Socrates' death-bed revelation in
Phaedo.
What is remarkable about Plato, and what marks him out as a reactionary, is that mystification and mythification are presented
after the First Greek Enlightenment (the physicists, sophists, and historians). Not that mythification is itself reactionary, but to present myths in a
deliberate,
self-conscious fashion,
after enlightenment, as a
response to enlightenment -- that is reactionary.
(However, one might point out that this is not entirely fair to Plato; if mythopoesis is a reaction to enlightenment, it is not necessarily
reactionary -- otherwise Blake's response to Newton would also be reactionary.)